University of Central Florida
gallaghr@mail.ucf.edu
Abstract: This
paper argues that Frith's (1992) account of the positive symptoms of
schizophrenia in terms of a disruption of metarepresentational self-monitoring
is inadequate in several specific ways.
More generally this paper argues against top-down explanations for the
loss of the sense of agency in such symptoms. In addition, even if delusions of control
might be explained by problems involved in motor control mechanisms involving
efference copy and comparators, there are good reasons why the same model
cannot explain thought insertion.
In place of such neurocognitive explanations, the author develops a
neurophenomenological explanation for the loss of the sense of agency and the
misattribution of actions and thoughts to others in such symptoms.
Key words: Schizophrenia, Frith, delusions of control, thought
insertion, agency, ownership, top-down, bottom-up explanations,
neurophenomenology.
In the past dozen years a number of theoretical models of schizophrenic symptoms have been proposed, often inspired by advances in the cognitive sciences, and especially cognitive neuroscience. Perhaps the most widely cited and influential of these is the neurocognitive model proposed by Christopher Frith (1992). Frith's influence reaches into psychiatry, neuroscience, and even philosophy. The philosopher John Campbell (1999a), for example, has called Frith's model the most parsimonious explanation of how self-ascriptions of thoughts are subject to errors of identification. "On reflection, it also seems that this is not just one possible theory; it is the simplest theory which has any prospect of explaining the sense of agency, and we ought to work from it, introducing complications only as necessary" (1999a, p. 612).
Not everyone agrees. In their recent analysis of alien voices and inserted thoughts in schizophrenia, Stephens and Graham (2000) offer a critique of Frith. Their criticism, however, although serious, is neither deep nor extensive. They outline three points. First, Frith fails to provide an adequate account of why a subject who experiences thought insertion would misattribute that thought to some other agent. Second, Frith does not clarify the distinction between thought insertion and thought influence. And third, Frith fails to explain how a subject can claim both that he is thinking the thought and that the thought is someone else's thought (Stephens and Graham 2000, pp. 141-143).[1] I suggest that this critique is not sufficiently deep in the sense that Stephens and Graham do not challenge Frith's cognitive framework, only certain failures within that framework. Indeed, as I'll indicate below, Stephens and Graham's own cognitive model shares certain important features with Frith's.
In this paper I propose a deeper and more extensive critique of Frith, one that challenges the cognitive framework that Campbell defends as the most parsimonious. This critique is based on a phenomenological approach that is informed by neuroscience, and in this sense it can be called a neurophenomenological analysis (Gallagher and Varela, 2003; Varela, 1996). The paper is divided into three sections. In the first I provide a brief outline of Frith's analysis. I explicate the phenomenological critique of this analysis in part two. In the final part I outline a neurophenomenological approach that addresses the various problems found in Frith's account.
Frith's model
Frith's account of positive symptoms such as verbal hallucinations, delusions of control, and thought insertion moves from an explanation of motor behavior to an explanation of cognitive experience. This strategy involves a transposition of certain neurological mechanisms responsible for motor control to the level of cognitive mechanisms responsible for monitoring and controlling thought processes. Across these different levels, the problem for the schizophrenic is the same: a failure in basic self-monitoring processes. To explicate Frith's model it will be helpful to use a distinction that Frith later adopts (Farrer and Frith, 2002) - the distinction between sense of agency and sense of ownership.[2]
Pre-reflective self-awareness may include a sense of agency (a sense of being the initiator or source of a movement, action, or thought) and a sense of ownership (a sense that it is I who am experiencing the movement or thought [Gallagher, 2000a, 2000b; Stephens and Graham, 2000], or what some phenomenologists refer to as the "myness" of the experience [e.g., Zahavi and Parnas, 1998]). In the normal phenomenology of voluntary or willed action the sense of agency and the sense of ownership coincide and are indistinguishable. In the case of involuntary or unintended movement, however, they are clearly distinguished. I may acknowledge ownership of a movement -- for example, I have a sense that I am the one who is moving or is being moved. I can thus self-ascribe it as my movement. I may rightly claim, however, that I am not the author of the movement, because I do not have a sense of causing or controlling the movement -- I have no sense of agency for it. The agent of the movement, for example, is the person who is pushing or pulling or manipulating my limbs.
Likewise, in the case of involuntary cognitive processes, I may acknowledge that I am the one who is thinking, but claim that the thoughts are not willfully generated by me. For example, certain unbidden thoughts or memories may impinge on my consciousness, even if I do not intend for them to do so, or even if I resist them (see Frankfurt, 1976; Graham and Stephens, 1994; Stephens and Graham, 2000). Melodies stay in our heads when we would rather think of something else, for example. In such cases, of course, we may not want to say that there is a specific agent for thinking. It is not that I think someone else is causing my thoughts or my experience. Nonetheless, my claim of ownership (my self-ascription that I am the one who is undergoing such experiences) may be consistent with my lack of a sense of agency.
Not unlike unintended movement and thought, positive symptoms of schizophrenia such as delusions of control and thought insertion, involve a disruption in the sense of agency, but not in the sense of ownership. Frith's (1992) cognitive model of schizophrenia as a disruption of basic self-monitoring processes can be understood to be a possible explanation of how self-ascriptions of thoughts and actions may be subject to errors of identification in regard to agency.
Frith is led to this view from observations of motor behavior in schizophrenia. Chronic schizophrenic patients suffer from a variety of movement disorders, and often make mistakes about the agency of various bodily movements. Not only do they fail to recognize their own agency in such cases, but schizophrenics suffering from delusions of control misattribute agency for their movements to someone or something else. Frith (1992, p. 66) provides an example: "The force moved my lips. I began to speak. The words were made for me." The motor action responsible for the speech is in fact the patient's own motor action, and the patient acknowledges that they are his lips that are moved, but he makes an error of identification concerning who produced this motion. Here the sense of agency, rather than the sense of ownership, is disrupted. That is, the patient knows that they are his lips and that he speaks, but seemingly his lips were moved, and the words were generated by someone else.
To explain this disruption in the sense of agency Frith turns to a classic theory of motor control which involves a hypothetical brain mechanism termed the comparator. The comparator model states that when a motor instruction to move is sent to a set of muscles, a copy of that instruction, the efference copy, is also sent to a comparator or self-monitoring system. Held (1961) suggested that efference copy sent to a comparator is stored there, and then compared to reafferent (proprioceptive or visual) information about the movement that is actually made. On this model my monitoring of my movement would seemingly have to wait for sensory feedback; it would come after the fact as verification that it was I who did the moving. As Campbell explains it,
[I]n the cases in which we do have a sense of agency, in which the movement performed is felt to be your own, what grounds that sense of agency is match at the relevant comparator between the efferent copy and the sensory feedback you have about the movement. What explains the feeling that it is you who moved your arm is that at the comparator, an efferent copy was received of the instruction to move your arm which matches the movement you perceive (1999a, p. 612).
In the case of the schizophrenic's motor experience, what explains his lack of a sense of self-movement, on this model, is the absence of a match between movement and efference copy at the comparator.
According to this sensory-feedback model if something seems to be going wrong with the action, it is quite possible to correct for it on the basis of this more or less concurrent self-awareness. Frith realizes that this model alone is not sufficient to explain motor control, however. A second component involved in the normal control of movement can also be interpreted in terms of a comparator model. In this respect, the comparator is understood to be part of a "forward" pre-motor system operating prior to the actual execution of movement and prior to sensory feedback (see Wolpert, Ghahramani and Jordan, 1995; and Frith, Blakemore and Wolpert, 2000 for an advanced version of this model). The forward model derives from an explanation of visuo-motor coordination. The visual system can distinguish between movements on the retina that are due to movements in the world, and movements on the retina that are due to movements of the perceiver's own body. In the latter case stability of the visual image is achieved by the motor system sending efference copy "to some monitoring system at the same time as a message is sent to the eye muscles" (Frith, 1992, p. 74). The efference copy alerts the visual system to compensate for self-generated or self-initiated movement. Frith refers to this as a monitoring of intentions to move (1992, pp. 74 and 81). The forward comparator thus functions to match efference copy with motor intentions, anticipating the movement, and it allows for quicker and automatic corrections to movement prior to any sensory feedback. This forward system not only assists in the generation of controlled action, it also generates a conscious sense that one is generating the action (Georgieff and Jeannerod, 1998; Jeannerod, 1994). Pre-action neuronal processes anticipate the actual motor performance and provide an online sense of agency that correlates to the sense of movement. In one's immediate phenomenology during action, agency is not represented as separate from the action, but is an intrinsic property of action itself, experienced as a perspectival source.[3]
Experiments have demonstrated that schizophrenics have problems with the forward monitoring of movement, but not with motor control based on sensory feedback. Non-schizophrenic subjects required to use a joystick to follow a target on a computer screen are able to use either visual feedback or the pre-action, more automatic process for correction of movement. In the first case, to correct a mistaken movement one depends on visual perception of one's hand. When subjects recognize the error they move to correct it. If visual perception of the hand is unavailable, however, the normal subject makes a quicker and smoother correction of errors. Such rapid error corrections presumably depend on the forward monitoring of motor intention, prior to any sensory feedback. Schizophrenic patients, however, find it difficult to monitor their own motor intentions at this level (Malenka et al., 1982). Like normal subjects they correct their errors when visual feedback is provided, but, unlike normal subjects, they often fail to correct their mistakes when deprived of visual feedback (Frith and Done, 1988).
In delusional experience of control the schizophrenic feels that he is not the agent of his movement. This loss of a sense of agency is explained by Frith as a disruption of efference copy in the central monitor, a dysfunction of the forward, pre-action aspect of the motor system. This makes good sense with respect to normal involuntary action: where a subject does not intend the action, there would be no pre-action preparation, no intention registered at the comparator. In the case of the schizophrenic' s delusion of control, however, since he is in fact the agent, the disruption of the sense of agency is explained by something going wrong with efference copy or the forward comparator mechanism.
According to the experimental data, the schizophrenic does seem able to correct movement errors if sensory feedback is available. Likewise, in the case of involuntary action, the sensory feedback system still seems to do its job, providing a sense that I am moving. Although things are likely to be more complicated at the neurological level, this suggests that the distinction between sensory-feedback control and forward pre-action control corresponds to the distinction between sense of ownership and sense of agency, respectively. That is, both in the schizophrenic's delusional experience of control and in the normal experience of involuntary action, the sensory feedback system tells the subject that it is he who is moving or being moved (providing a sense of ownership for the movement). With a disruption of efference-copy at the forward comparator, however, the system will fail to register a sense of agency, a sense that it is the subject himself who is the willful generator of the movement.
Can something like this model of motor control be applied to cognition? Frith (1992) thinks that it can (see Blakemore, 2000 for a good summary). He points out that this sort of self-monitoring mechanism is traditionally used in explaining motor, perceptual, and linguistic behavior (for example, Sperry, 1950; Von Holst and Mittelstaedt, 1950). Following Feinberg (1978), however, he postulates a similar mechanism for cognition -- specifically, for thought and inner speech. He suggests that defects in such mechanisms can explain phenomena such as thought insertion and auditory hallucination.
Frith proposes the following explanation of thought insertion.
Thinking, like all our actions, is normally accompanied by a sense of effort and deliberate choice as we move from one thought to the next. If we found ourselves thinking without any awareness of the sense of effort that reflects central monitoring, we might well experience these thoughts as alien and, thus, being inserted into our minds. (Frith, 1992, p. 81).
Frith's model assumes not only that thinking is a kind of action, but that, as in the case of a motor action, we experience an effortful intention. The intention to think, according to Frith, is the element that bestows a sense of agency for the thought. Normally, efference copy of the intentional generation of thought is sent to a comparator or central monitor, which also registers the occurrence of the actual thought, thus matching up intention and thought (Figure 1). So if efference copy is somehow blocked from reaching the central monitoring mechanism, thought occurs which seems not to be generated by the subject. If efference copy is blocked or goes astray, or is not properly generated, thinking still occurs, but it is not registered as under my control - it appears to be an alien or inserted thought. There is no match between intention and thinking.
Figure
1: Match at at a feedback comparator identifies thought as
happening
in one's own system; match at the forward comparator generates
a sense of agency.
In outline, we now have the basic framework that Frith uses to explain the delusional symptoms of schizoprhenia. The various mechanisms of control are meant to be cashed out in neurological terms. To these mechanisms, however, and as part of the way they work, Frith would add the operations of a higher-order cognitive level. Frith speaks of a conscious feeling of effort for a willed intention to think, and he equates this with a conscious monitoring of efference copy (1992, p. 86). Frith's analysis relies, not just on an intention to act (to move or to think), but on an awareness of the intention to act, and he defines this awareness as a case of "metarepresentation." Metarepresentation is a second-order reflective consciousness, "the ability to reflect upon how we represent the world and our thoughts." This is part of what it means to monitor our actions and, he claims, it is precisely what is missing or disrupted in the schizophrenic's experience. In schizophrenic delusions of control and inserted thought, there is a failure of metarepresentation; the metarepresentational monitoring of movement or thought breaks down.
A phenomenological critique of
Frith
Several aspects of Frith's model are phenomenologically problematic. A first set of problems pertains to Frith's characterization of the intention to think. In the case of thinking or conscious experience what role does something like an intention to think play? It is difficult to conceive of an intention to think prior to thinking itself, unless it is entirely a conscious preparation, as when I might decide to sit down and start thinking about a certain issue. In that case, however, the intention to think is itself a thinking, and an infinite regress begins to loom: do I require an intention to think in order to intend to think?
Stephens and Graham (2000) consider this objection, but not in relation to Frith's analysis. Rather they discuss an objection raised by Akins and Dennett (1986) against Hoffman's (1986) account of alien voices. Akins and Dennett suggest that the idea of having an intention to think leads to a "never-beginning regress of intentions to form thoughts" (p. 517). Stephens and Graham point out, however, that Hoffman's account concerns only the kind of thought that might be called inner speech, and just as we might accept the idea that someone may have an intention to say something, it is not so odd to accept the idea that someone may have an intention to say something in inner speech. They agree, however, that not all intentional thinking could be described as inner speech, and that the idea that there is an intention to think in every case would be unacceptable (pp. 81-82). Yet on Frith's model, an intention to think, and indeed, an awareness of that intention to think is required to provide a sense of agency for thoughts.
Campbell (1999a) suggests, as a corrective to Frith's characterization, that efference copy (and thus the intention to think that it represents) is not itself available to consciousness.[4] On this view, efference copy is part of a subpersonal and non-conscious process that generates an awareness of effort as thought itself is generated. To get the phenomenology right, Campbell moves the intention to think underground to a subpersonal mechanism. As thoughts are generated (something that might happen in any number of ways) efference copy is normally sent to a comparator. Thought generation involves subpersonal processes that subtend the thinking process. Ultimately this is to be cashed out in terms of neuroscience rather than phenomenology.
At the very least, then, we should say that most cases of normal thinking are neither prefaced by conscious intentions to think, nor followed by an introspective awareness of that intention. In the normal phenomenology, at least in the large majority of cases, there is not first an intention and then a thinking, nor thinking plus a concurrent but separate awareness of intention to think.
What Frith calls 'intention to think', then, may be part of a subpersonal, nonconscious process. When it works properly, it generates a sense of agency for our thoughts. Does the disruption of this process, however, explain the phenomenology of inserted thoughts?
As with movement, it is not always the case that my thinking is characterized as something I intend. There are unbidden thoughts that, as Frankfurt puts it, "strike us unexpectedly out of the blue; and thoughts that run willy-nilly through our heads" (1976, p. 240). I may just find myself thinking of something. Without a conscious act of recollection, particular memories may come to the fore, invading or disrupting my thoughts with elements of my past that may or may not be relevant to my present circumstance. Is there any kind of intention to think in such cases? If in such cases I do not have a sense of agency for my thoughts, still, I do not attribute my thoughts to someone else in the way that the schizophrenic does.[5] This means, however, that the lack of an intention to think (or the disruption of efference copy) is not doing all the work that Frith would like it to do in the case of schizophrenia. The absence of an intention to think, and hence, the lack of efference copy generated to represent that intention at the comparator level do not explain anything more than a relatively normal lack of a sense of agency. As Stephens and Graham point out in their critique of Frith's theory, it does not explain the attribution of thought to another agent, or why some thought might seem inserted for the schizophrenic. At best, in the absence of an intention to think we have unbidden thoughts, but not inserted thoughts.
If the failure of the efference copy/comparator mechanism fails to explain the phenomenology of inserted thoughts, specifically their misattribution to others, we can push things a bit further by asking ask whether we need the efference copy/comparator mechanism at all in the case of thinking? Campbell argues that Frith's model provides the most parsimonious explanation of the sense of agency for cognition. Yet Frith's model would add to the cognitive system a separate mechanism to generate a sense of agency for thinking. Is this necessary in a system that is already conscious?
In the case of visuo-motor control, efference copy serves a pragmatic, executive function rather than a verificational one. In effect, one system informs another system to make adjustments, with very practical effects -- for example, stability of the visual field, postural balance, and so forth. The function of efference copy is to inform the visual and vestibular systems that the organism, rather than the world, is moving. Even in the case where the motor system is simply updating and correcting itself, the purpose of efference copy is for motor control. Its purpose is not to verify (simply for the record?) that movement is taking place.[6] Nor is it primarily an information stream that discriminates between intended movement and non-intended movement. Its purpose is rather to instruct the motor or sensory system to make important adjustments. Is there anything like this happening in the thinking process?
One can certainly distinguish different cognitive systems -- memory systems, perceptual systems, and so on. But efference copy, as it is described by Frith, does not play a communicative role among these systems. Rather, on the Feinberg-Frith model, consciousness seems to be sending itself messages. Thus Campbell suggests, following Feinberg, that efference copy has the primary function of keeping thoughts on track, checking "that the thoughts you actually execute form coherent trains of thought" (1999a, p. 616). To keep thoughts coherent and on track, however, could only mean to keep them on a semantic track, that is, on a certain track of meaning or on a line of logical reasoning. It seems odd, however, to assign this task to a subpersonal, non-semantic mechanism when, simply put, we are already consciously aware of our thoughts and can keep track of them, and keep them on track, at a conscious level. Indeed, it seems more appropriate to grant this task to the kind of metarepresentational introspection that Frith talks about. I may indeed require a reflective introspection to make sure that my logical reasoning is on track, or that my thoughts form a relatively coherent whole. But all of this seems quite a different task from verifying that the thoughts that I am thinking are self-generated. Or is it?
Is there a relationship between maintaining a sense of coherency in thought and a sense of agency? One version of a positive answer to this question is given by Stephens and Graham (2000).
We propose that a person's sense that he is a thinker or agent of his mental activity - of his conscious thoughts and feelings - likewise depends on his conviction that his occurrent mental episodes express his intentional states. That is, whether a person regards a thought (subjectively) in him as something that he thinks, rather than a mere episode in his psychological history, depends upon whether he finds it explicable in terms of his conception of what he believes and desires. (p. 165)
In this respect, Stephens and Graham share part of the same framework that Frith constructs. Specifically, they agree that the sense of agency in some way depends on higher-order cognitive processes. For Frith, the sense of agency depends, at least in part, on the monitoring of a metarepresentational introspection of first-order phenomenal experience. Stephens and Graham seem able to do without Frithian subpersonal mechanisms, but they too require a second-order level of introspection to guarantee the agentive sense for thought.
[W]hether I take myself to be the agent of a mental episode depends upon whether I take the occurrence of this episode to be explicable in terms of my underlying intentional states (1994, p. 93).
depends upon whether I take myself to have beliefs and desires of the sort that would rationalize its occurrence in me. If my theory of myself ascribes to me the relevant intentional states, I unproblematically regard this episode as my action. If not, then I must either revise my picture of my intentional states or refuse to acknowledge the episode as my doing. (1994, p. 102).
The problem with this top-down approach is that there are many kinds of thoughts that may not be coherently integrated with a subject's system of beliefs or desires, but may nonetheless not seem to be inserted. For example, some instances of unbidden thoughts, or in the case of compulsive disorders, compulsive thoughts which do not express the patient's beliefs or desires and yet are not claimed by the patient to be inserted by others (see Gallagher, in press-a).
Frith proposes a model that is more hybrid than the one outlined by Stephens and Graham; that is, Frith's model involves both higher-order (metarepresentational) cognition and subpersonal mechanisms. It is not clear, however, how precisely these two components fit together. The fact that the comparator mechanism for conscious thought is subpersonal, means that the matching process seemingly involves both conscious and non-conscious elements. Campbell is right to say that efference copy is not something of which we are conscious. But on Frith's model we need to match that efference copy to the stream of thought itself, which is already a matter of consciousness. Supposedly the outcome of the match, the sense of agency, must also be conscious in some way -- a conscious sense that I am the one who is thinking. One might suppose, however, that the match process itself in the subpersonal comparator would not be conscious, (otherwise there would have to be a consciousness of something that remains non-conscious -- efference copy).
You have knowledge of the content of the thought only through introspection. The content of the efferent copy is not itself conscious. But it is match at the monitor between the thought of which you have introspective knowledge and the efferent copy that is responsible for the sense of being the agent of that thought. It is a disturbance in that mechanism that is responsible for the schizophrenic finding that he is introspectively aware of a thought without having the sense of being the agent of that thought. (Campbell, 1999b, p ?).
This kind of hybrid process seems less than parsimonious when the particular thing that we are supposedly monitoring - namely, our thought process - is already consciously available. On top of this, as we have seen, nothing in this hybrid system seems to explain why the schizophrenic who lacks a sense of agency goes on to misattribute agency to someone or something other than himself.
Campbell describes the comparator process as involving a form of introspection: "it is the match between the thought detected by introspection, and the content of the efferent copy picked up by the comparator, that is responsible for the sense of ownership of the thought."[7] Frith invokes the notion of metarepresentation, a full-fledged act of reflection, as part of the monitoring process. But a metarepresentational introspection again threatens infinite regress. Since metarepresentation is itself a thought, if I want to attribute this metarepresentation to myself, I would need to monitor it with a meta-metarepresentation. I would have to ask, in a further metarepresentational thought, Is this my metarepresentation? It would be an extra level of consciousness added to the comparator's verification process. My intention to meta-represent would have to generate its own efference copy, to be matched up on top of the original match. As I will suggest below, in the final section, in the case of thinking, which is already pre-reflectively conscious, even one level of metarepresentation for maintaining a sense of agency, or even one level of efference copy for purposes of keeping track of thoughts is redundant.
Not only does the need for metarepresentation in the normal case not seem phenomenologically parsimonious, but in regard to the claim that metarepresentation fails in the case of schizophrenia, it runs counter to some clinical accounts. In contrast to Frith's notion that there is a lack of metarepresentational self-monitoring in schizophrenia, some clinicians suggest that there may be too much of it. In principle, it seems possible for metarepresentation to go wrong in at least two ways. First, as Frith suggests, it might fail in such a way that the schizophrenic can be left without the ability to monitor his own experience. Second, however, as Sass (1992, 1998, 2000) suggests, metarepresentation can be generated in a hyperreflexive attitude, and as a result, the schizophrenic can over-monitor aspects of his own experience. It also seems possible that the disruption of metacognition could be selectively Frithian and Sassian. As a result of a failure to monitor certain aspects of his experience the schizophrenic may enter a hyperreflexive attitude about what is absent from or odd about his experience. A schizophrenic may have great difficulties with attention, not because of a complete lack of attention, but because he is attending in a high degree to certain aspects of his experience that are different. The failure of self-monitoring may in some instances be that there is too much of it going on (Sass, 1998; Zahavi and Parnas, 1998). Exactly how we should think of the role of higher-order cognition (whether it fails due to a lack of metarepresentation, or due to a surplus of hyperreflexivity) is still uncertain. We return to this point below.
If, in the case of schizophrenia, one of the comparator mechanisms described by Frith breaks down or is put out of operation, why do not all thoughts seem alien?[8] If either the "Thought Generator Mechanism" fails to generate efference copy, or the central monitor fails to register efference copy, how do we explain that these mechanisms do seem to work normally sometimes, since not all of the schizophrenic's thoughts are experienced as inserted thoughts? I will refer to this as the selectivity problem or the problem of the episodic nature of positive symptoms. Selectivity involves the fact that when a particular thought seems inserted, there are other aspects of conscious experience that do not seem inserted. Either simultaneously with, or immediately after the thought that seems inserted, there is the sense or feeling or realization that it is inserted. But this sense or feeling or realization does not itself feel inserted. That is, the subject, in recognizing a thought as inserted, does not claim that his recognition of this fact is inserted. He is rather speaking in his own voice when he complains about the inserted thought. That this is the case is clear, not only from empirical reports by patients, but by logical necessity. The subject's complaint that various thoughts are inserted depends on a necessary contrast between thoughts that seem inserted and those that do not seem inserted -- and at a minimum, the thoughts that constitute the subject's complaint cannot seem inserted. If all thoughts were experienced as inserted by others, the subject would not be able to complain "in his own voice," so to speak. He would not maintain a sufficient sense of ownership for his cognitive life, or a sense of cognitive "space" by which to define an insertion.
This selectivity problem cannot be explained by a failure of a comparator, since such a failure should also affect the sense of recognition that the thought is inserted. A theory that would credit a higher order cognitive process (a metarepresentation, or an evaluative introspective judgment) founders on this same problem. It would need to explain why a higher order cognition that fails to generate a sense of agency for a particular thought or experience is itself experienced as self-agentive. Why is it that a subject can have a sense of agency for one thought, but not for the other? Quite obviously the phenomenology here needs to constrain the cognitive explanation.
A further problem for Frith's model involves the specificity of positive symptoms. In this regard, in cases of thought insertion, specific kinds of thought contents, but not all kinds appear to be thought inserted. I suggest that no explanation that remains totally on the subpersonal level will be able to explain this specificity. It is not simply that in experiences of thought insertion patients only occasionally experience thoughts coming into their minds from an outside source. Rather, their experiences are very specific, and are sometimes associated with specific others. For example, a schizophrenic may report that thoughts are being inserted by a particular person, and that they are always about a specified topic. In auditory hallucination the voice always seems to say the same sort of thing. Such specificity phenomena seem to have a semantic and experiential consistency and a personal-level complexity that cannot be adequately explained by the disruption of subpersonal mechanisms alone.
A more general problem with Frith's analysis concerns the global nature of schizophrenia and its various symptoms. Schizophrenics have problems, not only with movement and self-reference, but also, among other things, with working memory, episodic and autobiographical memory, and narrative construction (Gallagher, 2003). Is it possible to reduce all of these problems to one central difficulty with self-monitoring, or to one comparator mechanism which is neurologically ill-defined? If the subject experiences both delusions of control and inserted thoughts, does this mean that two separate comparators - one in the motor system and one in the conscious thought system - malfunction independently? Or is the implication that one comparator covers both movement and thought? Or is something more global involved? At best Frith proposes similar mechanisms for motor action and cognition, but does not clarify how they might be related, or whether the embodied processes of motor control and cognition are connected.
Farrer and Frith (2001) have shown
contrasting activation in the right inferior parietal cortex for perception of
action caused by others, and in the anterior insula bilaterally when action is
experienced as caused by oneself.
One possible explanation for the involvement of the right inferior
parietal cortex in the discrimination between self-agency and other-agency is
suggested by Jeannerod (1999).
Namely, actions performed by others are perceptually mapped in
allocentric coordinates. Farrer
and Frith note that "there is strong physiological evidence that the
inferior parietal cortex [involves this] kind of remapping ... to generate
representations of body movements in allocentric coordinates. (p. 601)
In contrast, they suggest, the role of
the anterior insula in providing a sense of self-agency involves the
integration of three kinds of signals generated in self-movement: somatosensory
signals (sensory feedback from bodily movement, e.g., proprioception), visual
and auditory signals, and efference copy associated with motor commands that
control movement. "A close correspondence between all these signals helps
to give us a sense of agency" (p. 602).
Neuroimaging studies by
Decety et al. (2002) and Chaminade and Decety (2002), provide more evidence for
the involvement of the inferior parietal lobule in discriminating agency. Decety et al. (2002) have shown more
activation in the left inferior parietal lobule when a subject imitates another
person (and thus has an appropriate sense of agency for such actions) compared
to more activation in the right inferior parietal lobule when the other person
imitates the subject.[10] They conclude that "the
lateralization of the inferior parietal lobule activity may be critical for
distinguishing consequences of actions generated by the self from those
initiated by others, especially when confusion may occur."
Other studies show that
lesions in the right parietal lobe can lead to difficulties in attributing
actions. For example, lesions in the right parietal cortex can cause a
disturbance of the sense of ownership for one's limbs (as in neglect or alien
hand syndrome). Also, in psychiatric and neurological patients self-awareness
disorders have been linked to metabolic abnormalities in the right inferior
parietal cortex. In schizophrenic
patients the feeling of alien control (delusions of control) during a movement
task has been associated with a increased activity in the right inferior
parietal lobe (Spence, et al., 1997).
Of course things are likely more complicated than this, in both normal and schizophrenic experience. As suggested in the Frithian analysis, the sense of agency for motor action may depend on a pre-action, forward motor control mechanism that matches motor intention and efference copy of the motor command. The proper timing of such a match may depend on the proper functioning of the supplementary motor area, the premotor, and prefrontal cortexes, and such functions are known to be disrupted in schizophrenic subjects with delusions of control (Fourneret and Jeannerod, 1998, Georgieff & Jeannerod, 1998; Haggard and Eimer, 1999; Haggard and Magno, 1999; Malenka et al., 1982). For reasons outlined above, however, mechanisms that explain motor action may not be the mechanisms that best explain disruptions in the sense of agency for cognition. Indeed, there may be a more general or basic disruption of neuronal processes that affect not just the sense of agency for motor action, but disrupt the sense of agency for cognitive experience (e.g., thought insertion). The sense of agency for thought may depend on the anticipatory aspect of working memory, which is manifested in the pre-reflective structure of phenomenal experience (Gallagher, in press-b). Just such problems with working memory are to be found in schizophrenic subjects with delusions of control (see, Daprati, et al., 1997; Franck et al., 2001; Singh et al., 1992; Vogeley, et al. 1999).
If this in fact is an accurate characterization of schizophrenic experience at the level of first-order phenomenal consciousness, then in some respects it seems clear that the subject's second-order report on such experience is not mistaken. The subject correctly reports her experience, that she experiences herself as the owner of, but not the agent of the movement or thought; she correctly attributes ownership but not agency for the thought. This is not a mistake or misinterpretation, as suggested by Stephens and Graham, but a report of what the subject actually experiences. The experience, summarized in a first-person, albeit abstract way, is this: "I am not the agent of my movement or thought."[11] But, of course, this is not a complete statement, for the patient goes on to say "Someone else is controlling my movement or thought." If the only problem were a lack of agency, then there would be no difference between the phenomenology of passive, involuntary movement, or unbidden thoughts, and schizophrenic delusions. The explicit delusional component involves the subject's misattribution of agency to another person (or machine, or thing). In this regard, pace Frith (1992), a lack of a sense of self-agency does not add up to an attribution of action to others. Here there appears to be two possible explanations of the misattribution.
(a) The cause of the misattribution is based on inferences made at the higher-order level of attributive consciousness.
In this case, the attribution of
agency to another is not the result of a misinterpretation or cognitive
accounting that would force the subject to infer that since he is not the agent,
someone else must be, or a supplemental account generated by introspection, the
odd result of a productive narrative; rather, it is a genuine report of what is
truly experienced. This is not to
rule out the fact that odd, paradoxical, and wildly delusional narratives are
often generated as the illness develops.
The initial motivation for such narratives, however, may be shaped by
processes that start out as completely rational at the second-order level - that
is, a completely correct report of what the subject experiences.
Here I will cite only one
piece of evidence for this view (see Gallagher, in press-a, for further
discussion). Recent brain imaging
studies (using PET or fMRI) show activation of a
partially overlapping cortical and subcortical network that includes structures
directly concerned with motor execution (motor cortex, dorsal and ventral
premotor cortex, lateral cerebellum, basal ganglia) and areas concerned with
action planning (dorsolateral prefrontal cortex and posterior parietal cortex)
in the following situations: during my action, during the observation of
another person's action, and during the imaginary simulation of my own or
another's action (Decety et al, 1997, Grezes and Decety, 2001; Jeannerod, 1999). The brain areas activated when I engage in specific
intentional actions are in large part the same brain areas that are activated
when I observe someone else engage in the same activity.[12] A number of scientists suggest that
just such overlapping or shared representations may play some part in our
ability to simulate the thoughts and attitudes of others (Blakemore and Decety, 2001; Chaminade et al., 2001; Decety,
2002; Jeannerod, 2001). This
suggests that if something goes wrong with this neuronal "Who" system
(Georgieff and Jeannerod, 1998) our own movement, or even our own thoughts, may
be experienced as initiated by someone else.[13] There is good evidence that this is
what happens in some schizophrenic patients. (Jeannerod, et al., 2003).
These observations suggest that whatever higher-order cognition is like in schizophrenia (whether it is hypo or hyper), it is not led, solely on its own (that is, by its own mistaken inferences or misinterpretations or corrupt theories), to misattributions of agency. Rather, the ipseity [9], which includes the sense of agency that is normally implicit in any intentional act, is disrupted at the first-order phenomenal level, and the effects of this disruption become an object of reflective introspection (Zahavi and Parnas, 1998). This is the point at which to evoke hyperreflexivity - not as a higher-order cognition that disrupts ipseity and generates alterity, but as a reflection that discovers an alterity that is already manifesting itself on the first-order phenomenal level, generated by neuronal processes that are abnormal.
Two problems remain: the selectivity and the specificity of delusional and inserted thoughts. The selectivity problem may simply depend on the neurological disruptions being occasional. Delusional states may be generated when the shared representations that allow for a discrimination between my movement and someone else's movement, or my thought and my simulation of someone else's thought, are disturbed. This may be infrequent early in the illness, and more frequent as the illness develops.
The specificity problem, that is, the fact that the schizophrenic delusions refer to specific people or things or situations or content, is likely more complex. In part it may be simply an accident of when and in what context the shared representations misfunction, and who happens to be around. In part it may depend on the subject's own personal history, emotional attitudes and states, and relations with others (see Gallagher, 2000b; Gallagher and Varela, 2003). And in part it may be intensified by an introspection that shades off into confabulation.
Such considerations do not
amount to a complete explanation of schizophenia, or even of the positive
symptoms that we have been discussing.
There is much more to be said about the nature and temporal structure
(including an anticipatory structure) of first-order, pre-reflective
self-consciousness, the "ipseity"
that gets disrupted by neurological processes that dysfunction (Gallagher, in
press-b; Gallagher, 2000b; Gallagher and Varela, 2003). There is also much more to say about
the working of higher-order cognition, and the generation of peculiarly
schizophrenic narratives (Gallagher, 2003). My claim, however, is that the framework provided by this
neurophenomenological approach can sustain these other analyses better than a
framework designed around a purely cognitive or a Frithian neurocognitive
approach.
Akins, K. A.
and Dennett, D. 1986. Who may I say is calling? Behavioral and Brain
Sciences 9: 517-18.
Blakemore, S-J. 2000. Monitoring the self in schizophrenia: The role of internal models. In D. Zahavi (ed). Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological Perspectives on Self-experience (pp. 185-202). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Blakemore,
S-J. and Decety, J. 2001. From the perception of action to the understanding of
intention. Nature Reviews, Neuroscience 2: 561-567.
Campbell, J. 1999a. Schizophrenia, the space of reasons and thinking as a motor process. The Monist, 82 (4): 609-625.
Campbell, J.
1999b. Immunity to error through
misidentification and the meaning of a referring term. Philosophical Topics,
26: 89-104.
Chaminade and Decety,
2002. Leader or follower? Involvement of the inferior parietal lobule in
agency. Neuroreport 13 (1528): 1975-78.
Chaminade,
T., Meary, D., Orliaguet, J-P.,
and Decety, J. 2001. Is perceptual
anticipation a motor simulation? A PET study. Neuroreport 12
(17): 3669-74
Decety, J. 2002. Naturaliser
l'empathie. L'Encéphale 28: 9-20.
Decety J, Chaminade T,
Grezes J et al. Neuroimage 15, 265-272 (2002).
Decety, J., Grezes, J.,
Costes, N., Perani, D., Jeannerod, M., Procyk, E., Grassi, F. and Fazio, F.
(1997) Brain activity during observation of actions: Influence of action
content and subject's strategy. Brain,
120, pp. 1763-77.
Daprati, E., Franck, N., Georgieff, N.,
Proust, J., Pacherie, E., Dalery, J., Jeannerod, M. (1997). Looking for the
agent: An investigation into consciousness of action and self-consciousness in
schizophrenic patients. Cognition,
65, 71-96.
Farrer, C., Frith C.D. 2001. Experiencing oneself vs. another person as being the cause of an action: the neural correlates of the experience of agency. NeuroImage 15: 596-603.
Feinberg, I. 1978. Efference copy and corollary discharge: Implications for thinking and its disorders. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 4: 636-40.
Fourneret, P. and Jeannerod, M. 1998. Limited conscious monitoring of motor performance in normal subjects, Neuropsychologia 36: 1133-1140.
Franck, N., Farrer, C., Georgieff, N., Marie-Cardine, M., Daléry, J., d'Amato, T., and Jeannerod, M. 2001. Defective recognition of one's own actions in patients with schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry, 158: 454-59.
Frankfurt, H. 1976. Identification and externality. In A. O. Rorty (ed). The Identities of Persons (pp. 239-51). Berkeley: University of California Press.
Frith, C. D. 1992. The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Frith, C. D., Blakemore,
S.-J. & Wolpert, D. M. 2000. Abnormalities in the awareness and control of
action. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 355,
1771-1788.
Frith, C. D.,
and Done, D. J. 1988. Towards a neuropsychology of
schizophrenia. British Journal
of Psychiatry, 153: 437- 443.
Gallagher S. (In press-a). Sense of agency and higher-order cognition: Levels of explanation for schizophrenia. Cognitive Semiotics, 2 (2003).
Gallagher, S. (In press-b). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. (2003). "Self-narrative in schizophrenia," in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, ed. A. S. David and T., Kircher (pp. 336-357). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Gallagher, S. 2000a. Philosophical conceptions of the self: implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4 (1): 14-21
Gallagher, S. 2000b. Self-reference and schizophrenia: A cognitive model of immunity to error through misidentification. In D. Zahavi (ed). Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological Perspectives on Self-experience (pp. 203-39) Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Gallagher, S. and Varela, F. (2003). Redrawing the map and resetting the time: Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy.
Georgieff, N. and
Jeannerod, M. 1998. Beyond consciousness of external
events: A Who system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7: 465-77.
Graham, G. and Stephens, G. L. 1994. Mind and mine. In G. Graham and G. L. Stephens (eds). Philosophical Psychopathology (pp. 91-109). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Grezes, J. and Decety, J.
2001. Functional anatomy of
execution, mental simulation, observation, and verb generation of actions: A
meta-analysis. Human Brain
Mapping, 12: 1-19.
Haggard, P. and Eimer, M. 1999. On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research 126: 128-33.
Haggard, P. and Magno,
E. 1999. Localising awareness of
action with transcranial magnetic stimulation. Experimental Brain Research 127: 102-107.
Held, R. 1961. Exposure-history as a factor in maintaining stability of perception and coordination. Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, 132: 26-32.
Hoffman, R.
1986. Verbal hallucinations and
language production processes in schizophrenia. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9: 503-517.
Holst, E. von and
Mittelstaedt, H. 1950. Das
Reafferenzprinzip (Wechselwirkungen zwischen Zentralnervensystem und
Peripherie). Naturwisenschaften, 37: 464-76.
Jeannerod, M. 2001. Neural simulation of action: A unifying
mechanism for motor cognition. Neuroimage,
14, S103-S109.
Jeannerod, M. 1999. To act or not to act: perspectives on
the representation of actions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, A 52:1-29
Jeannerod, M. & Frak, V. 1999. Mental imaging of motor
activity in humans. Currrent Opinions in Neurobiology, 9: 735-9
Jeannerod,
M., Farrer, C., Franck, N., Fourneret, P., Posada,
A., Daprati, E. Georgieff, N. 2003.
Action recognition in normal and schizophrenic subjects. In: The Self
and Schizophrenia, T. Kircher and A. David
(Eds). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kinsbourne, M. 1995. Awareness of one's own body: An attentional theory of its nature, development, and brain basis. In J. Bermúdez, N. Eilan, and A. Marcel (eds). The Body and the Self (pp. 206-223). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Malenka, R. C., Angel, R. W., Hampton, B. and Berger, P. A. 1982. Impaired central error correcting behaviour in schizophrenia. Archives of General Psychiatry, 39: 101-107.
Posada, A., Franck, N., Georgieff, N. and Jeannerod, M.
2001. Anticipating incoming events: An impaired cognitive process in
schizophrenia. Cognition, 81: 209-225.
Sass, L. 2000. Schizophrenia, self-experience, and the so-called negative symptoms. In D. Zahavi (ed). Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological Perspectives on Self-experience (pp. 149-82). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Sass, L. 1998. Schizophrenia, self-consciousness and
the modern mind. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 5: 543-65.
Sass, L.
1992. Madness and Modernism: Insanity in the Light of Modern Art,
Literature, and Thought. New York: Basic Books.
Singh, J. R., Knight, T., Rosenlicht, N., Kotun, J. M., Beckley, D. J. and Woods, D. L. 1992. Abnormal premovement brain potentials in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research, 8: 31-41.
Spence SA, Brooks DJ,
Hirsch SR et al. Brain 120, 1997-2011
(1997).
Sperry, R. W. 1950. Neural basis of the spontaneous
optokinetic response produced by visual inversion. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 43: 482-89.
Stephens, G. L. and Graham,
G. 2000. When Self-Consciousness Breaks: Alien Voices and Inserted Thoughts.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Varela, F. J. 1996. Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3 (4): 330-49.
Vogeley, K., Kurthen, M.,
Falkai, P., Maier, W. (1999). The human self construct and prefrontal cortex in
schizophrenia. The Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness:
Electronic Seminar (http://www.phil.vt.edu/assc/esem.html).
Wolpert, D. M., Ghahramani, Z, and Jordan, M. I. 1995. An internal model for sensorimotor integration. Science, 269: 1880-82.
Zahavi, D. and Parnas, J. 1998. Phenomenal consciousness and self-awareness: A phenomenological critique of representational theory. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5: 687-705.
[1] I think it would be
possible to defend Frith against this last charge. His account does not neatly distinguish between sense of
agency and sense of subjectivity (or ownership), an insightful distinction
found in Graham and Stephens (2000; also see Gallagher, 2002a, 2002b) that
helps to explain how the schizophrenic can say that he finds in his own mind
(subjectivity) a thought that is caused by someone else (agency), but the neurological
picture drawn by Frith is surely consistent with this distinction. We can also note that in more recent
papers the does in fact employ the distinction between sense of agency and
sense of ownership (e.g., Farrer and Frith, 2002).
[2] As indicated in Note 1,
I think that Frith's (1992) analysis is consistent with this distinction. One version of this distinction was
first put forward by Graham and Stephen (1994). They distinguished between
"attributions of subjectivity" and "attributions of agency."
Graham and Stephens explain these attributions, however, to be the product of
an introspective inference (also see Stephens and Graham, 2000). One attributes agency to oneself, for
example, on the basis of a reflective acknowledgement that one caused the
action. In contrast, I understand
the senses of ownership and agency to be experiential aspects, pre-reflectively
implicit in the phenomenology of action.
They are generated in a first-order phenomenology, not by a second-order
introspective cognition, but by neurological processes responsible for action
control (see Gallagher 2000; Gallagher, in press-b).
[3]Marcel (in press).
Experimental research on normal subjects supports the idea that such agentive
awareness of action is based on central motor processes that precede action and
that translate intention into movement, rather than on actual feedback from
movement or from peripheral effort associated with such movement (Fourneret and
Jeannerod, 1998). Research which
correlates initial awareness of action to recordings of the lateralized
readiness potential and with transcranial magnetic stimulation of the
supplementary motor area, strongly indicates that one's initial awareness of a
spontaneous voluntary action is based on anticipatory or pre-movement motor
commands relating to relevant effectors (Haggard and Eimer, 1999; Haggard and
Magno, 1999).
[4] Kinsbourne (1995)
suggests, with regard to intentions to move, that such intentions do not
persist long enough to be included in awareness, and that the movement itself
"rapidly supervenes and supplants the intention" (p. 214).
[5]Of course it is possible to attribute
thoughts in my mind to someone else, but in a very ordinary way -- for example,
in listening closely to a speaker, one might say that the speaker's thoughts
are being inserted into one's mind.
[6]In contrast to the idea that efference
copy performs a verificational role (Held 1961; Campbell, 1999a).
[7]Campbell (1999b) -- emphasis added. Campbell does not distinguish clearly
between sense of ownership and sense of agency.
[8]This objection was raised by Louis Sass
at the NEH institute on Mind, Self, and Psychopathology, Cornell University,
1998. One can see this problem in
Frith's description of the neurophysiology associated with the positive
symptoms of schizophrenia.
"Positive symptoms occur because the brain structures responsible
for willed actions no longer send corollary discharges to the posterior parts
of the brain concerned with perception.
This would be caused by disconnections between these brain regions"
(1992, p. 93). One would need to
explain why these disconnections are only manifested in some but not all
instances.
[10] In Chaminade and Decety
(2002) bilateral activity in the inferior parietal cortex was found in
conditions that involved confusion about the origin of the action. In experiments in which subjects are
required to lead someone else around (taking the lead in moving an image around
on a computer screen), more activity is apparent in the right inferior parietal
cortex than in the contrasting situation where the subject is asked follow
someone else's movement (as they move the image on the computer screen). In the latter case, involving less of a
sense of agency, and more a sense of passive control, or being acted upon, more
activation occurs in the left inferior parietal cortex than in the right.
[11] Even if we were reticent to accept the schizophrenic's own
reports of such experience, of which there are many, behavioral studies support
this interpretation. See Frith and
Done (1988); Posada et al., (2001).
[12] In the premotor cortex and
the supplemental motor area (SMA), the overlap between imagined and observed
actions is almost complete (Decety et al, 1997, Grezes and Decety, 2001;
Jeannerod, 1999; Jeannerod and Frak, 1999; Jeannerod,
2001).
[13] "This relative
similarity of neurophysiological mechanisms accounts for both the fact that
actions can normally be attributed to their veridical author, and that action
attribution remains a fragile process. Indeed, there are in everyday life
ambiguous situations where the cues for the sense of agency become degraded and
which obviously require a subtle mechanism for signaling the origin of an
action" (Jeannerod, et al., 2003).